Aristole - Virtue Ethics

DP Barrett - Aristotle’s Virtue Ethics

Aristotle (384-322 BCE) was a Greek philosopher, and was the pupil of Plato, but his philosophical ideas differed wildly from Plato’s. Plato can be described as a Rationalist, because he tried to solve philosophical problems with reason, discussion, and contemplation. Meanwhile Aristotle, the son of a doctor, believed that it was best to look at the world and largely based his conclusions of observation, which makes him more of an Empiricist. In ancient Greece ‘philosophy’ included all sciences and intellectual pursuits, and Aristotle wrote about almost everything, including physics, zoology, politics, economics, biology, and drama. Aristotle’s moral philosophy centres on the key concepts eudaimonia and virtue.

 
The Purpose of Life: Eudaimonia
Aristotle begins his moral treatise, The Nicomachean Ethics, by stating that the goal of life is happiness, because simple observation tells us that this is what everyone desires: “what is the highest of all practical goods? Well, so far as the name goes, there is pretty general agreement, It is happiness say both ordinary and cultured people.”

The word ‘happiness’ is the regular translation of the Greek word ‘eudaimonia’, however, it is a very imperfect translation and misleads many readers in to thinking that Aristotle is advocating a life of pleasure and enjoyment. Eudaimonia literally means ‘having good spirits’ (eu = good, daimon = spirit) and it has a connotation of being loved by the gods so that everything in your life is going well. A more appropriate translation might be ‘success’ or ‘flourishing’ or perhaps even ‘fully functioning.’ What Aristotle is saying is that we all want a good quality life, a life that satisfies all of a person’s needs.

Aristotle’s ideas about what constitutes a good life are connected to his ideas on human nature and its functions. There are four key factors to consider here. Firstly, like all living beings we need to stay alive, so part of functioning well means being healthy and fit. Secondly, like all animals we naturally have desires for pleasure, and we seek to avoid pain, so a fully functioning good life should involve pleasure. Thirdly, like many other animals we are social beings, so we require friendships and it is a function of our nature to serve society. Fourthly, we are rational beings capable of knowledge, speech, and wisdom, and we alone have this ability, hence one of the functions of human nature is to reason and learn. Aristotle takes health as an obvious part of a good life, but considers three different common opinions as to what makes a good life connected to these functions concerning which is most important: pleasure, honour, and wisdom.


Pleasure
The average person believes that eudaimonia, the good life, consists in pleasure. Firstly this means being healthy and free of pain, but it also means getting what you want, enjoying things, and avoiding pain and suffering. Such a life would be typified by not having to work, eating good food, getting drunk, having lots of sex, and so on, and it may be connected to wealth and materialism. The later philosopher JS Mill described these as ‘lower pleasures.’

This may be the life that most of us want, but to Aristotle it is not the essence of eudaimonia. Aristotle described the life of pleasure as a ‘bovine existence’ because it is the kind of life that animals seek, and it does not satisfy the higher parts of human nature. Aristotle argued that as social beings we need to do our duties to our community, and a life of seeking pleasure will get in the way of this. Moreover, the life of pleasure is not pleasing to the intellect and gets in the way of knowledge and wisdom. A person who simply lives for pleasure may have to use some intelligence to get it, but has not achieved eudaimonia because his life is deficient; he is not fully functioning or making use of the intellectual potential in human nature.


Friendship / Honour
Aristotle paints friendship as the main aim of life because it is the kind of life that most of us are capable of achieving. As social animals we need and desire friends: “nobody would choose to live without friends even if he had all the other good things.” To have friendship is to live in good relations with our neighbours, to be esteemed by them, and to be useful to them, and so on. In particular Aristotle is referring to doing your duties to society, and this is what he means by ‘honour.’ This means things like paying your taxes, obeying the laws, helping other people, doing jobs for your community, and also being willing to fight to defend your society and being willing to lay down your life for it. It is about being a respectful person and a good citizen: “man is born for citizenship.”

The life of honour is important to Aristotle, and all people should try to honourable in this way. For Aristotle a good life includes health, wealth, and pleasure, but these are not the ultimate factors, a good life must also include friendships and honour. It often means giving up on personal enjoyment for the sake of the community so that you can fulfil your duties: “even if the good of the community coincides with that of the individual, it is clearly a greater and more perfect thing to achieve and preserve that of a community.” The life of honour involves learning skills which are useful to social success, and which help to make you a good citizen, i.e. the ‘moral virtues.’ The lifestyle of honour also requires the use of the intellect, so it requires the ‘intellectual virtues’ but it does not aim at knowledge for its own sake.


Knowledge and Wisdom
This is the life the philosopher aims at, but in modern terms we might also say that it is what scientists, mathematicians, and other thinkers and investigators also aim at. Such people enjoy reflection and the pleasures of the mind, and they use their brains as best they can to try and understand the world. JS Mill described these as ‘higher pleasures.’ Again, a good life should include health, pleasure, and friendships, but for Aristotle the life which focuses on knowledge and wisdom is the highest form of eudaimonia, particularly since it is reason and wisdom which separates mankind from the animals. To reason well and learn about and understand the world is the specific function of human beings because only we are capable of it. However, Aristotle recognises that very few people are capable of achieving this rich life of knowledge and understanding, because not everyone has the intelligence to grapple with philosophy and science, nor do they have the time, which is why Aristotle says that most people should aim primarily at honour and friendship.


The Virtues
The Greek word for virtue was arête, which means ‘excellence.’ A virtue is an excellent character trait or skill which helps a person to fulfil their functions and achieve eudaimonia. In order to perform a function well various skills and traits are required, for example, in order to be a good policeman you would need to be observant, assertive, healthy, trained in combat, rational under pressure, honest, and so on. As another example, in order to be a good student you need virtues such as punctuality, diligence, the ability to listen and take good notes, politeness, intelligence, and so on. For Aristotle it is the possession of virtues which makes you a good person, that is, a good quality human being capable of achieving eudaimonia, whether it be the life of honour or the life of knowledge. He states that there are two main types of virtue, the moral virtues and the intellectual virtues.


The Moral Virtues
Moral virtues help us to act correctly in a social environment, helping us to control our behaviour and interact with others well. They also control the irrational and emotional part of our nature, the part of us which seeks pleasure and wants to avoid pain. In Aristotle’s view there is nothing wrong with having emotions, you would not be human without them, but they still must be controlled and it is important for them to be appropriate. The moral virtues include things such as courage, generosity, temperance, honesty, helpfulness, and patience. Moral virtues are cultivated by habit and it can take years of practice to master them; to become a generous person I must get into the habit of being generous, and in doing so I learnt to move away from the vice of meanness. As Will Durrant put it, “we are what we repeatedly do, excellence therefore is not an act, but a habit.”

Aristotle provides a set of 12 virtues, which are in the table on the next page. According to Aristotle the moral virtues are subject to ‘the doctrine of the mean’ which is the idea that each virtue is midway between the twin vices of deficiency and excess. When it comes to confidence you can go wrong in two ways, either by not having enough confidence or by having too much. If you are a soldier and you have no confidence then you will run away and you will not be able to perform your job adequately, and this deficiency is the vice of cowardice. But similarly being over-confident will make you foolhardy and reckless meaning that you take silly risks and similarly you will end up failing in your duties.

The Doctrine of the mean is often misinterpreted as suggesting an attitude of ‘moderation in all things’ but this is an over simplification, it is about striking the right balance for the situation. If a pupil misbehaves then it is acceptable for a teacher to get angry and shout at them in order to modify the pupil’s behaviour, however, the teacher must not get so angry that he loses control. Similarly, he must not be so patient that he allows the pupil to get away with unacceptable behaviour. This is where we have the virtue of patience, which is control of your anger; it is a vice to lose your temper too easily, but it is also a vice to never lose it at all even when anger is warranted and necessary, something which Aristotle dubs a ‘lack of spirit.’

Similarly, truthfulness is a mean. This is because it is often possible to exaggerate about events, or to exaggerate about your own achievements, and this is the vice of boastfulness. On the other hand you can understate how things are, and undersell yourself, which is also a flaw.


Sphere of action
Deficiency
Mean
Excess
Fear and confidence
Cowardice
Courage
Rashness:
Taking foolish risks
Pleasure and pain
Insensibility
Temperance
Licentiousness:
Lack of restraint
Anger

Lack of spirit
Patience
Irascibility:
Being quick to anger
Self-expression

Understatement
Truthfulness:
Accurately reporting how things are.
Boastfulness:
Exaggerating about yourself.
Conversation
Boorishness:
Being dull and uninteresting.
Wittiness:
Being entertaining.
Buffoonery:
Being a fool / not being serious enough.
Social conduct
Cantankerousness:
Being unhelpful
Friendliness:
Being helpful
Obsequiousness:
Being a brown nose.
Shame
Shamelessness
Modesty:
Decent behaviour, speech, dress, etc.
Shyness
Indignation

Malicious enjoyment:
Pleasure at other people’s misfortune.
Righteous Indignation:
Anger at injustice.
Envy:
Jealousy of other’s successes and wealth.
Getting and spending (minor)
Illiberality:
Meanness.
Liberality:
Generosity.
Prodigality:
Wastefulness.
Getting and spending (major)
Pettiness:
Being small.
Magnificence:
Being large.
Vulgarity:
Showing off.
Honour and dishonour (minor)
Unambitiousness
Proper ambition
Ambition
Honour and dishonour (major)
Pusillanimity:
Timidity.
Magnanimity:
Being forgiving.
Vanity:
Vindictiveness

 
Ethics is about learning which actions are appropriate to the situation, and it is the virtues which control action via controlling the emotions that lead to action. In many ways mastering the moral virtues is like learning to drive, you have to learn to balance the pedals and you cannot give precise formulations for how this must be done, it depends on the situation, but you can always go wrong by doing too much or too little. The best thing you can do is follow the example of others who are viewed as successful and learn by your mistakes.

We can easily see that these virtues are not just concerned with the narrow ideas of morality as right conduct, they relate to life in general and to being well liked and respected too. For Aristotle being entertaining is a virtue, and it is a character flaw to be boorish and have no sense of humour, but equally it is a flaw to go too far and act like a clown. When it comes to spending your money you should be generous and charitable and help others, but you should not be excessive and wasteful so that you bankrupt yourself. If you are very rich it is good to be ‘magnificent’ and share your money, but it is not good to show off and be vulgar.

Clearly Aristotle thinks that a good life should include pleasures; to live a life without pleasure and enjoyment is insensibility and is not a good life, however, the pleasure in your life must be moderated by reason. It is not sensible to enjoy so much food that you become unhealthy, and when pleasure is getting in the way of social duties or education then you must put pleasure aside and resist it. Similarly, pain is to be feared, but sometimes it is necessary so you have to learn to endure it. This is where the virtue of temperance in important. Similarly, it is good to be generous, but not to the extent of being wasteful and ending up in poverty.

 
The Intellectual Virtues
The doctrine of the mean does not apply to the intellectual virtues, rather, the more intelligent you are the better. Intellectual virtues are needed by everyone, because they are required in order to live well and succeed in your ventures, for example, they are needed to make your business work, or work out how best to please friends, or how to build a house, or how to make important political decisions. They are most strongly required by those who dedicate themselves to knowledge and wisdom. Aristotle was an elitist and literally believed that those who were most intelligent were better quality human beings than those who lacked intelligence. The intellectual virtues are as follows:

  • Technical skill – e.g. knowing how to build a house.
  • Scientific knowledge – knowing facts about biology, geography, physics, etc.
  • Prudence – knowing how to balance your needs with those of others.
  • Intelligence – mathematical abilities and similar mental skills.
  • Wisdom – ideas about what to do gained through long years of experience.
  • Resourcefulness – knowing how and where to get the best information from.
  • Understanding – this goes beyond knowing facts, but sees the whole issue and all the complex difficulties associated with decision making.
  • Judgement – this is essentially moral judgement, and for a judgement to be good it has to take in to account what is right and good for all concerned.
  • Cleverness – this is important as it helps you to work out how to get what you want, but on its own without good judgement it can be unscrupulous, for example, a clever person without moral scruples could use his intelligence to con you.

The Cardinal Virtues
Aristotle argues that some virtues are more important than others, and these are what he names the ‘cardinal virtues.’ These are courage, temperance, wisdom, and justice. Temperance is required to control our urges for pleasure and to avoid pain, as these can often lead to immoral actions. Courage allows a person to do what they know is right, even when doing so is difficult. Wisdom is key to an intelligent understanding of the world and justice is the habit of giving people what they deserve, such as respect, fair treatment, or rewards and punishments, something that wisdom helps you to learn about.


Strengths of Aristotle’s Virtue Ethics
There are many reasons to support Aristotle's vision of ethics, in particular his emphasis on having a good character, aiming to make the most of your potential, and improving yourself through building good habits.


1) Most people do aim for happiness / eudaimonia
It seems true that the vast majority of people do aim to live a good quality life, and also true that people have differing ideas about what a good life is. It may be argued that Aristotle’s list of three views on the good life (pleasure, honour, and knowledge) is too narrow, for example, people might also aim at money, sporting excellence, art and creativity, fame, and so on. We might also say that honour and friendship are different things as many people care a lot about their friends and family, but little about society as a whole. None the less, Aristotle has certainly identified some of the main things we do indeed aim for in life.

Many ‘Neo-Aristotelians’ argue that a combination of these factors is needed for a good life, for example, Rosalind Hursthouse says that success in life should not be measured in purely material terms: “someone who lacks wealth and power may still count their lives to be a success – ‘I am rich in the things that matter’, one says, ‘my children, my friends, my books, my memories, my job…’ And it is the possibility of this non-material sense of ‘success’ which makes it a suitable translation of ‘eudaimonia.’”


2) Good people do tend to have virtues
It seems true that we expect good and successful people to have virtuous traits like honesty, courage, and intelligence. If you point out any good or successful person from history, such as Martin Luther King Jr. or Marie Curie, you will be able to notice virtues in their character such as courage, generosity, intelligence, perseverance, diligence, and wittiness. Aristotle wants us to aspire to be like these excellent people, and to follow role models. The same counts for people in your local community whom you consider to be good, they will have a variety of virtuous habits such as friendliness, truthfulness, temperance, and wisdom.


3) It allows for greater scope in moral judgements
One strength is that Aristotle’s ethics gives us a greater scope to judge people and cultures with. Instead of simply saying “this is a bad person” we can be more specific, recognising that most people have a mixture of virtues and vices. For instance, we can say that Oskar Schindler was a virtuous man in some ways, as he had the skills to run a business and the compassion to save over 1100 Jews from the Holocaust, but at the same time he was also unfaithful to his wife, extravagant, and happy to use Jewish slave labour. Instead of looking at a foreign culture such as the Taliban in Afghanistan and saying “these people are bad because of how they treat women” we might instead want to say “these people excel in virtues such as courage and temperance, but they are deficient in the virtues of friendliness and justice.”


4) It encourages people to be excellent
Virtue ethics encourages people to develop their characters and become the best people they can be. It is not focused on a set of rules like “do this!” or “don’t do this!” but instead is focused on character and says “be this!” Aristotle is encouraging people to take their potential talents and develop them and bring them in to actuality, rather than wasting your talents. His ethics also encourages people to be good members of their community, and to follow admirable role models. In many ways Abraham Maslow’s views on ‘self-actualisation’ and the hierarchy of needs are a modernised version of Aristotle’s views on eudaimonia.


Criticisms of Aristotle’s Virtue Ethics and Some Responses
There have been many criticisms leveled against Aristotle's view on ethics, including the idea that all virtues can be abused for bad ends, and that it does not actually give a clear guide to how to behave.


1) All of the virtues can be abused
Immanuel Kant argued that virtue ethics was an insufficient moral philosophy because every virtue can be abused for immoral purpose, for example, you can use courage to assault someone, and you can use intelligence to plan a bank robbery. Kant argued that what morality really requires is a list of rules to follow, and this is something that Aristotle fails to provide us with. It may be that virtues are needed to help you to follow the rules, but without these rules virtue is insufficient; virtue alone does not make a good person.

Counter point: Aristotle says that there are intellectual virtues such as wisdom, judgement, and prudence, and that these should help you to make your decisions about what is best to do. Arguably it is precisely these things that Kant and other enlightenment philosophers like Hobbes or Bentham appeal to when trying to formulate their own lists of rules and principles. Moreover, virtues such as friendliness and modesty would surely suggest being kind to others.


2) Virtue Ethics can be unhelpful in making moral decisions
As just noted, Aristotle does not provide his readers with rules to live by, indeed, he openly states that because life is so complex you cannot have specific rules that apply absolutely at all times. Some may see this as a wise approach, however, arguably this leave us with little or no direction when it comes to answering specific moral questions such as whether abortion should be allowed. Arguably it is not very helpful to say ‘be brave’ or ‘be kind’ or ‘be wise’ in these cases as it is unclear which course of action is the most courageous or compassionate or sensible. The idea of having virtues is the idea of developing the habit of performing the right actions at the right times, and having the appropriate feelings to the right extent, but this is all very vague and is arguably unhelpful in actual decision making.

Counter point: Aristotle would reply that moral decisions are given their substance via the community you live in, so essentially he agreed with cultural relativism. Every different society expects different behaviour of its citizens, and as social beings we ought to follow the customs of our society. Aristotle would also point to the virtue of practical wisdom, which is all about doing what you think is most beneficial to yourself and your community; no matter which society you live in it is clear that certain rules will be required which make the society function more effectively, such as rules on justice, truthfulness, and not harming each other; despite the variations, general rules like these are found everywhere.


3) Exactly which traits are virtues?
There have been many different ideas about virtue over the years, and it is not fully clear which character traits should be seen as virtuous. Aristotle describes wittiness as a virtue because being entertaining helps to make you socially successful, but some people would reject this as unnecessary for you to be a good person. Aristotle thought that pride and ambition were virtues, but Christians would see these as sinful as people ought to be humble. Christian thinkers agreed that the most important virtues were courage, temperance, wisdom, and justice, but they also added faith, hope and charity to this list of Cardinal Virtues: faith in God, hope for the afterlife and that good will defeat evil, and loving kindness towards others. We do not find any religious notions in Aristotle’s list of virtues, and atheists would also reject these as virtues, for example, David Hume says that wise people only believes in things there are evidence for, meaning that having faith and hope contradicts the virtue of wisdom, in his opinion. Christians also argue that that chastity is a virtue, but Hume derided it as ‘monkish’ and Aristotle would have called it ‘insensibility.’

Alisdair MacIntyre argues that conceptions of which character traits are virtues have changed over time depending on culture and conditions, for example, in times when there are great threats of conquest people who are brave and violent often become viewed as virtuous, e.g. Achilles in Homer’s Iliad, whereas in our modern materialistic society those with business skills or beauty might be considered to have the most admirable characteristics. In the recent past patriotism was considered a virtue, but many people today see it as a vice which can lead to prejudices. In short, it seems that it is difficult to come to solid conclusions as to which character traits and habits are virtues and which are vices, because opinions vary.

 
4) Why is service to the community good?
Aristotle argues that service to the community is a necessary component of a good life, and that for most people it should be the major focus of their lives; this is what he calls the life of ‘honour.’ Aristotle is claiming that you should willingly do duties to your society and be a good citizen, rather than just satisfying your own desires. In modern times this might mean things like volunteering for charities, being an active member of your church or school community, getting involved in politics, doing an important social job like teaching, nursing, or policing, and it may also mean defending your country, such as fighting in wars. We may praise those who do this, but is it necessary for everyone to live this way?

For many people what is important in making a good life is their friends and family rather than society at large. Aristotle’s view is largely based on his belief that human beings are naturally social beings, and that we therefore have natural duties to our society, but many philosophers oppose this view. Thomas Hobbes argued that each person was an individual who should be purely concerned with his own needs, and that we only join society because it helps to provide us with personal safety and prosperity through co-operation.


5) Why is wisdom and knowledge best?
Aristotle argues that the best life for a human being is one centred around knowledge and wisdom. A good life should include pleasure, health, and social duties, but for Aristotle the major focus ought to be the things that JS Mill called the ‘higher pleasures.’ We can question this; why should a life of academic study be superior to a life of sporting success? Why should intellectual development be more important than having good friends, being a good spouse, and bringing up a family? What valid reason is there to say that a man who plays chess and completes crosswords is having a better life than one who enjoys playing pool and having a few beers? Many people would reject Aristotle’s views as snobbery, and say that so long as life is pleasurable it is good, as Jeremy Bentham put it prejudice apart, the game of push-pin is of equal value with the arts and sciences of music and poetry.”


6) Aristotle’s Elitism
According to Bertrand Russell, Aristotle’s virtue ethics encourages humans to despise each other for lacking the qualities that one is supposed to possess, or for possessing them in lesser degrees than oneself. People who are not courageous, or who lack temperance, or generosity, or intelligence will be seen as lower quality human beings, and as deserving of less respect. Aristotle’s theory is elitist literally saying that some human beings are better than others.

Counter point: surely it is normal and natural to judge people based on their abilities and character? And surely it is better to judge them by “the content of their character” rather than by the colour of their skin, or gender, or sexuality, and so on?

Peter Vardy make a similar point, that in Aristotle’s times it was only the rich males who were capable of pursuing the life of honour or wisdom, whilst most of the population were just a poorly paid underclass or even slaves. Aristotle actually supported slavery arguing that less intelligent people should be governed by the more intelligent. In Aristotle’s views some people were born too lacking in intelligence to properly govern their own lives, and these people should be directed by the intelligent. As far as Aristotle was concerned some people are born to plan and rule, others are born to work and follow, and this was for mutual benefit.

Counter point 1: We could argue that Aristotle was a product of his times when slavery was common. Some Neo-Aristotelians argue that we should reinterpret Aristotle as simply pointing out that relationships are often unequal because one party has superior skills and knowledge to the others, for example, in places of work it is normal to have bosses and subordinates. What is problematic for most modern minds is the notion that highly skilled and intelligent people have greater dignity and value than others, meanwhile, Friedrich Nietzsche simply accepted it as a truth that some people are better than others and worth more, and saw the idea of equality as originating in those who were low quality and didn’t like being at the bottom of society’s heap.

Counter point 2: In Aristotle’s times most people were uneducated, so it may easily have seemed that some people were lower than others and that they needed to be controlled, like children or animals. Today, when we have universal education, it can be seen that practically everyone is capable of a variety of achievements in their lives. Richard Norman argues that we should try to reinterpret Aristotle’s Ethics as a call to recognise the humanity in all people and help them to flourish and achieve their potential through things such as education.


7) Aristotle and the Disabled
According to Aristotle, health and fitness is part of the function of a human being, so it follows that those who are physically disabled or chronically ill cannot achieve eudaimonia, as their life is deficient in some respects; such people are not fully functioning and are not achieving ‘the good life.’ Similarly, since intelligence is part of the function of a human being, those who are mentally disabled cannot achieve eudaimonia. Many people perceive this as prejudiced and unfair.

Counterpoint: It can be argued that people can still flourish to some degree despite being disabled, for example, Aristotle would probably have highly respected Stephen Hawking for his intellectual and scientific achievements, after all, the intellect is our highest function according to Aristotle. None the less, Aristotle would still say his life was deficient in significant respects, and given the choice the fact is most people would rather not be disabled.

 
8) Is virtue ethics selfish?
Virtue theory has been criticised as being self-centred because it is generally seen as being about getting the best life for yourself, and achieving your own personal happiness or ‘eudaimonia.’ It seems that when you help other people you are not doing it for their sakes, but for your own personal self-development, which is hardly altruistic and moral.

Counter point: arguably this is not a good criticism as Aristotle actually thought of the community as more important than the individual; to Aristotle the good of the community and the good of the individual are capable of going hand in hand, because only through living in a well-developed and peaceful society can pleasure, friendship, and knowledge be achieved. Additionally, human beings do tend to genuinely care for each other and their happiness can depend on that of others. Remember that for Aristotle man is a naturally social animal.


9) Can you actually control your character?
The theory is centred around the idea of having a strong character, and developing your virtues, and Aristotle emphasises the role of getting into good habits so that acting well becomes second nature. However, some people would question the extent to which we can control our character. One view is that we have little or no control over our personality and habits, because who we are is down to factors we can’t change such as our DNA and upbringing: we have certain personalities and these cannot easily be changed.

On the other hand, some people regard character as something that is far too flexible to be relied up, as your character is malleable and subject to change, especially depending on the situation. It is very easy to end up acting in completely ‘uncharacteristic’ ways when you are put into unusual situations, and it is usually these unusual situations which call for us to make important moral choices. The people who partake in genocide during wars are often ordinary people with friends and families, who would not harm others in ordinary life. If your character can be pushed and pulled around by your situation, and the society and people around you, then how much responsibility do you have for it?


Summary and Conclusions
Aristotle’s theory shows an awareness of what human beings want in life, happiness or ‘eudaimonia’ and it provides us with what many see as an encouraging view of human achievement, however, some would argue that Aristotle’s views on what makes a good life are merely his own prejudices and opinions. Virtue seems to be required for a person to be considered ‘good’, but philosophers such as Kant argue that his lack of rules leave us devoid of direction and without a guarantee that ‘virtues’ or ‘skills’ will not be abused.

No comments:

Post a Comment