DP Barrett - Deontology & Teleology
Absolutism and Relativism
With this
simplistic approach to morality we are looking only at the actions themselves
and not the contexts in which they take place, and this makes solving moral
dilemmas very difficult, take this classic example from Plato’s Republic: A man has leant you his axe, but he has now
become mad and enraged at someone; he arrives at your door asking you to give
the axe back to him because he needs it to kill the man who has offended him. We
have a moral dilemma on our hands because on the one hand you owe the man the
axe and he has a right to it, so you are effectively stealing by refusing to
give it back as well as breaking your promise to return it to him; on the other
hand you surely have a duty to save lives – saving lives is right and good. One
rule suggests that you should give the axe back, the other to keep it and refuse
to give it back. What to do?
One
possible resolution is to say that both courses of action would in some way be
wrong, but that stealing the axe would be the “lesser of two evils.” But the problem here is that if we are just
saying “x is wrong” and we are not yet talking in terms of how or why it is
wrong then we do not have a particular reason to think that one action is better
or worse than any other. Another
connected problem arises, it seems wrong to say that actions are simply right no
matter what, and wrong no matter what. For example, imagine I knock a total
stranger out, take a knife, cut him open, and then remove his heart. This all sounds terribly immoral, but what if
I am a doctor and this stranger is a patient whose life I hope to save via a
heart transplant? It seems that actions
can be wrong in one circumstance, right in another; it would be wrong to run
down the high street knocking people over, but there’s nothing wrong with doing
it on a rugby pitch, in fact that’s part of the aim of the game and everyone on
the pitch consents to it.
This leads
us to consideration of the distinction between an absolutist view of morality and a relativist view of morality. An
absolutist view states that a certain action is wrong no matter what the
circumstances so that it can never be done, for example, that murder is wrong no
matter what and so killing is never allowed, not even in war or in
self-defence. Meanwhile the relativist
will say that an action might be wrong most of the time, but that sometimes it
might be justified or moral, for example, stealing would normally be wrong, but
sometimes it is the lesser of two evils, for example if you are poor and your
only choice is between stealing food and starving then stealing is justified.
Similarly, stealing the axe from the man who wishes to use it to kill people is
not only justified, but actually the exactly right thing to do.
Interestingly, the circumstances in which an action happens are
often built in to the very words we use; no one (or rather, very few people)
would say that sex in itself was wrong and immoral, but we automatically
distinguish between sex with a partner and sex with someone other than your
partner – this is what the word ‘adultery’ means. Adultery is cheating and it is widely
condemned; we may not say that sex is always wrong, but we might well say that
adultery is always wrong. The problem is that without providing reasons for why
an action is right or wrong in these circumstances or those circumstances it is
difficult to see what should be accepted and what should not, and what can be
justified and what should not. This
leads us on to the more advanced distinction between teleology and deontology.
Teleology
The word ‘telos’ is
Greek for ‘goal’ or ‘aim.’ The core idea in teleological thinking is that
actions are right and wrong because of the goal they are aiming to produce. It is a way of justifying actions, for
example by saying that a war is justified because whilst it will cause pain and
misery, the outcome will outweigh that pain and misery; the outcome is desirable
so the means of getting that outcomes is justified. From this perspective
actions by themselves are morally neutral, so that something like lying or
stealing or even killing is neither good nor bad, it can only be considered good
or bad in relation to the consequences that it produces. For example, Act Utilitarians (who follow the moral
ideas of Jeremy Bentham) believe
that the aim of moral action should be to produce human happiness, therefore, if
lying will make people happy in a particular situation, then you ought to lie
and the lie you have told is very good indeed. Similarly, if killing a dictator
will bring a greater amount of freedom, prosperity, and happiness to the nation
he controls, then killing him would be the best possible thing to do.
Essentially the end you are pursuing can justify the means or method you use to
get to it. Teleology is also known as Consequentialism.
In many circumstances teleological thinking is morally
unproblematic; it makes sense to burden everyone with taxation (something which
is unpleasant) if the net gain is safety, health, and prosperity thanks to the
existence of the police, army, schools, hospitals, fire services, and so on. In
many ways taxation could be viewed as a form of theft, or even slavery (working
for the benefit of others with no direct pay), but the unhappiness caused is
outweighed by the happiness created. Remember that teleology is not about the
rightness and wrongness of actions themselves, but is about the way you justify
actions. A teleological thinker will not say “all lying is wrong” but instead
will say “sometimes lying is wrong because it causes unhappiness” or “sometimes
lying is right because it causes happiness.”
It would be tempting to equate teleological thinking
with relativism, but this is not so. It is important to note that not all
teleological thinkers will agree on the same courses of action, for example, John Stuart Mill argued that in order
for people to be happy they need to feel safe and secure, and therefore,
creating a strict bill or rights is the best way to ensure the greatest
happiness for society. JS Mill formulated a theory called Rule Utilitarianism which says that
society needs to make rules and stick to them strictly. Mill would be strongly
against treating people the way suggested above. He would say that actions such
as murder should be strictly prohibited by law and that they are always wrong,
but not because they just are intrinsically, rather, they are wrong because they
help to create unhappiness. Similarly, Rule Utilitarianism would ban dishonesty
and lying, but not because these are wrong in themselves, but because of their
general consequences; lying can, on some occasions, create happiness, however,
it also creates mistrust, which makes daily life harder and therefore
contributes to unhappiness.
Deontology
Deontology is the
opposite philosophical approach to ethics, again it does not simply say “this
action is wrong and is always wrong” but rather, deontologists judge actions
based on the principles involved. One deontologist might argue that since life
is sacred this means that killing should never happen, and thus war cannot be
allowed as it involves killing. Meanwhile a different deontologist might say
that we all have a duty to defend our country and this can mean that it is right
to go to war and kill people. For deontologists what’s crucially important in
ethics are the principles involved, things like justice, duty, honour, honesty,
and so on. First and foremost,
deontology rejects the idea of basing moral decisions around consequences
because deontologists believe that if something is immoral it does not suddenly
become moral out of convenience or in order to achieve a goal. Suppose that an
innocent man was accused of a crime he did not commit and that a large mob have
gathered demanding that he be handed over to them to be lynched, otherwise they
will riot causing the destruction of property and the lives of anyone who gets
in their way. According to teleological
thinking the town’s sheriff should just hand him over because his death is preferable to the immense
damage and loss of life the mob will cause.
But a deontologist would probably say that the consequences were
irrelevant and that the sheriff should be standing up for justice, not giving in
to injustice or threats of violence: he should do his duty as a police officer
come what may. Indeed, the word “deontology” derives from the Greek word for
‘duty’ or ‘that which is binding.’
Let’s consider the example above again concerning the
possibility of abducting some homeless people to test drugs on for a cure to
AIDS. A deontologist would appeal to principles such as the sanctity of life and
self-ownership as reasons not to abduct and use them this way; yes, there is the
potential for huge benefits to mankind from these experiments, but you simply
cannot treat people like that because it is unjust and breaks important moral
principles.
Religious
morality is characteristically deontological because it is based around the
principle of doing what God commands, no matter what the consequences, even if
it means personal unhappiness or death. Religious morality can be absolutist as
it often consists in following rules like the Ten Commandments, but there are
some relativist teachings also, for example, some Christians believe that Jesus’
command to always act out of love means sometimes breaking rules to help people.
The most famous deontological thinker was Immanuel Kant who argued that we ought
never to do anything to another person that we would not want done to ourselves.
Kant argued that we should treat all others with respect: no one should be
simply used as a means to an end, there should always be respect for their
personhood and right to determine their own lives. For Kant what was important
was doing your duty, treating rational beings with respect, and not harming
others in order to achieve your goals no matter whether those goals are personal
or for the wellbeing for others.
Of course, deontology also has its problems, for
example, principles can clash as they did with the madman and the axe you owe
him. Respect for property and keeping promises are important principles, but
upholding them and returning the axe means you will have to forget about the
sanctity of life and your duty to protect lives. There are some people who would
justify returning the axe because then you are doing nothing wrong yourself, you
are merely returning property to its rightful owner; what the owner does with it
is not your concern. Other deontologists, however, would suggest that some
principles are more important than others and that in this case you should not
return the axe, because life is more important than promise keeping and
property.
Deontology is also often accused of standing in the
way of progress and the achievement of human happiness by limiting what we can
do. How many millions of lives could be saved if we would just test our
potential AIDS cure on just a few dozen unlucky people? Are we not losing sight of one of the most
important parts of morality, the idea that actions should be performed to better
people’s lives? Some people would say that deontological thinkers are
impractical idealists who do not see the big picture. Some would argue that we
live in a complicated world where difficult decisions have to be made, and
sometimes we just need to forget about principles. Think about the sheriff
facing the angry mob; he has a duty to stand up for justice, but he also has a
duty to maintain law and order. In refusing to hand the innocent man over he is
failing to keep the peace and this will lead to lots of innocent people being
harmed, for example, having their shops looted. Reality is messy, real life is
full of grey areas and sometimes you’ve got to do the ‘best’ thing rather than
the ‘right’ thing.
Again it would be easy to associate deontology with
absolutism, but this is inaccurate; many deontologists might support a wholesale
prohibition on any killing because of the sanctity of life principle, but on the
other hand another deontologist might say that in the interests of justice, or
in the interests of doing your duty to your country, it may be necessary to go
to war and kill people. Here we have some deontologists agreeing with an
absolutist perspective, and others taking a more relative approach. WD Ross held that duties should be
ranked, for example, our duty to return borrowed property to its rightful owners
is ‘trumped’ or outranked by our duty to save lives, and this is why it is wrong
to give the axe back to the madman.
However, a key problem is this: how can we rank the duties? Saving lives seems to be a more important
duty than telling the truth or not stealing property, but how do we actually
make this decision about what’s more important?
Ross suggested we do it on a case by case basis using intuition; is this
a strong enough answer? Isn’t it more accurate to say that we are turning to the
consequences in order to decide what is the more important principle?
Summary
For many people ethics is a simplistic matter whereby actions are just right or just wrong and that is all; this is an absolutist view, however, others argue that morals must be relative to the situation. In order to solve debates about what the rules should be we need to look at the justifications for them, and these tend to fall under one of two categorise – teleological views judge actions by their consequences, whilst deontological views concern themselves with the principles involved and argue that consequences are irrelevant. Average people will tend to pick up on and use ideas from both perspectives but philosophers will tend to stick to one perspective.
For many people ethics is a simplistic matter whereby actions are just right or just wrong and that is all; this is an absolutist view, however, others argue that morals must be relative to the situation. In order to solve debates about what the rules should be we need to look at the justifications for them, and these tend to fall under one of two categorise – teleological views judge actions by their consequences, whilst deontological views concern themselves with the principles involved and argue that consequences are irrelevant. Average people will tend to pick up on and use ideas from both perspectives but philosophers will tend to stick to one perspective.
No comments:
Post a Comment